Real Analysis Mathematics Pdf

A strange attractor arising from a differential equation. Differential equations are an important area of mathematical analysis with many applications to science and engineering.

We begin by discussing the motivation for real analysis, and especially for the reconsideration of the notion of integral and the invention of Lebesgue integration, which goes beyond the Riemannian integral familiar from clas-sical calculus. Usefulness of analysis. As one of the oldest branches of mathematics. Established Honours program in Mathematics were awarded in 1960. While at Windsor, he continued publishing his research results in logic and analysis. In this post-McCarthy era, he often had as his house-guest the prolific and eccentric mathematician Paul Erdos, who was then banned from the United States for his political views. Chapter 1 Mathematical proof 1.1 Logical language There are many useful ways to present mathematics; sometimes a picture or a physical analogy produces more understanding than a complicated equation.

Real analysis is one of the flrst subjects (together with linear algebra and abstract algebra) that a student encounters, in which one truly has to grap-ple with the subtleties of a truly rigourous mathematical proof. As such, the course ofiers an excellent chance to go back to the foundations of mathematics - and in particular, the construction. Buy Real Analysis: A Long-Form Mathematics Textbook on Amazon.com FREE SHIPPING on qualified orders. ABOUT ANALYSIS 7 0.2 About analysis Analysis is the branch of mathematics that deals with inequalities and limits. The present course deals with the most basic concepts in analysis. The goal of the course is to acquaint the reader with rigorous proofs in analysis and also to set a firm foundation for calculus of one variable (and several.

Mathematical analysis is the branch of mathematics dealing with limitsand related theories, such as differentiation, integration, measure, infinite series, and analytic functions.[1][2]

These theories are usually studied in the context of real and complex numbers and functions. Analysis evolved from calculus, which involves the elementary concepts and techniques of analysis.Analysis may be distinguished from geometry; however, it can be applied to any space of mathematical objects that has a definition of nearness (a topological space) or specific distances between objects (a metric space).

  • 2Important concepts
  • 3Main branches
  • 5Applications

History[edit]

Archimedes used the method of exhaustion to compute the area inside a circle by finding the area of regular polygons with more and more sides. This was an early but informal example of a limit, one of the most basic concepts in mathematical analysis.

Mathematical analysis formally developed in the 17th century during the Scientific Revolution,[3] but many of its ideas can be traced back to earlier mathematicians. Early results in analysis were implicitly present in the early days of ancient Greek mathematics. For instance, an infinite geometric sum is implicit in Zeno'sparadox of the dichotomy.[4] Later, Greek mathematicians such as Eudoxus and Archimedes made more explicit, but informal, use of the concepts of limits and convergence when they used the method of exhaustion to compute the area and volume of regions and solids.[5] The explicit use of infinitesimals appears in Archimedes' The Method of Mechanical Theorems, a work rediscovered in the 20th century.[6] In Asia, the Chinese mathematicianLiu Hui used the method of exhaustion in the 3rd century AD to find the area of a circle.[7]Zu Chongzhi established a method that would later be called Cavalieri's principle to find the volume of a sphere in the 5th century.[8] The Indian mathematicianBhāskara II gave examples of the derivative and used what is now known as Rolle's theorem in the 12th century.[9]

In the 14th century, Madhava of Sangamagrama developed infinite series expansions, like the power series and the Taylor series, of functions such as sine, cosine, tangent and arctangent.[10] Alongside his development of the Taylor series of the trigonometric functions, he also estimated the magnitude of the error terms created by truncating these series and gave a rational approximation of an infinite series. His followers at the Kerala School of Astronomy and Mathematics further expanded his works, up to the 16th century.

The modern foundations of mathematical analysis were established in 17th century Europe.[3]Descartes and Fermat independently developed analytic geometry, and a few decades later Newton and Leibniz independently developed infinitesimal calculus, which grew, with the stimulus of applied work that continued through the 18th century, into analysis topics such as the calculus of variations, ordinary and partial differential equations, Fourier analysis, and generating functions. During this period, calculus techniques were applied to approximate discrete problems by continuous ones.

In the 18th century, Euler introduced the notion of mathematical function.[11] Real analysis began to emerge as an independent subject when Bernard Bolzano introduced the modern definition of continuity in 1816,[12] but Bolzano's work did not become widely known until the 1870s. In 1821, Cauchy began to put calculus on a firm logical foundation by rejecting the principle of the generality of algebra widely used in earlier work, particularly by Euler. Instead, Cauchy formulated calculus in terms of geometric ideas and infinitesimals. Thus, his definition of continuity required an infinitesimal change in x to correspond to an infinitesimal change in y. He also introduced the concept of the Cauchy sequence, and started the formal theory of complex analysis. Poisson, Liouville, Fourier and others studied partial differential equations and harmonic analysis. The contributions of these mathematicians and others, such as Weierstrass, developed the (ε, δ)-definition of limit approach, thus founding the modern field of mathematical analysis.

In the middle of the 19th century Riemann introduced his theory of integration. The last third of the century saw the arithmetization of analysis by Weierstrass, who thought that geometric reasoning was inherently misleading, and introduced the 'epsilon-delta' definition of limit.Then, mathematicians started worrying that they were assuming the existence of a continuum of real numbers without proof. Dedekind then constructed the real numbers by Dedekind cuts, in which irrational numbers are formally defined, which serve to fill the 'gaps' between rational numbers, thereby creating a complete set: the continuum of real numbers, which had already been developed by Simon Stevin in terms of decimal expansions. Around that time, the attempts to refine the theorems of Riemann integration led to the study of the 'size' of the set of discontinuities of real functions.

Also, 'monsters' (nowhere continuous functions, continuous but nowhere differentiable functions, space-filling curves) began to be investigated. In this context, Jordan developed his theory of measure, Cantor developed what is now called naive set theory, and Baire proved the Baire category theorem. In the early 20th century, calculus was formalized using an axiomatic set theory. Lebesgue solved the problem of measure, and Hilbert introduced Hilbert spaces to solve integral equations. The idea of normed vector space was in the air, and in the 1920s Banach created functional analysis.

Important concepts[edit]

Metric spaces[edit]

In mathematics, a metric space is a set where a notion of distance (called a metric) between elements of the set is defined.

Much of analysis happens in some metric space; the most commonly used are the real line, the complex plane, Euclidean space, other vector spaces, and the integers. Examples of analysis without a metric include measure theory (which describes size rather than distance) and functional analysis (which studies topological vector spaces that need not have any sense of distance).

Formally, a metric space is an ordered pair(M,d){displaystyle (M,d)} where M{displaystyle M} is a set and d{displaystyle d} is a metric on M{displaystyle M}, i.e., a function

d:M×MR{displaystyle dcolon Mtimes Mrightarrow mathbb {R} }

such that for any x,y,zM{displaystyle x,y,zin M}, the following holds:

  1. d(x,y)=0{displaystyle d(x,y)=0}if and only ifx=y{displaystyle x=y} (identity of indiscernibles),
  2. d(x,y)=d(y,x){displaystyle d(x,y)=d(y,x)} (symmetry), and
  3. d(x,z)d(x,y)+d(y,z){displaystyle d(x,z)leq d(x,y)+d(y,z)} (triangle inequality).

By taking the third property and letting z=x{displaystyle z=x}, it can be shown that d(x,y)0{displaystyle d(x,y)geq 0} (non-negative).

Sequences and limits[edit]

A sequence is an ordered list. Like a set, it contains members (also called elements, or terms). Unlike a set, order matters, and exactly the same elements can appear multiple times at different positions in the sequence. Most precisely, a sequence can be defined as a function whose domain is a countabletotally ordered set, such as the natural numbers.

One of the most important properties of a sequence is convergence. Informally, a sequence converges if it has a limit. Continuing informally, a (singly-infinite) sequence has a limit if it approaches some point x, called the limit, as n becomes very large. That is, for an abstract sequence (an) (with n running from 1 to infinity understood) the distance between an and x approaches 0 as n → ∞, denoted

limnan=x.{displaystyle lim _{nto infty }a_{n}=x.}

Main branches[edit]

Real analysis[edit]

Real analysis (traditionally, the theory of functions of a real variable) is a branch of mathematical analysis dealing with the real numbers and real-valued functions of a real variable.[13][14] In particular, it deals with the analytic properties of real functions and sequences, including convergence and limits of sequences of real numbers, the calculus of the real numbers, and continuity, smoothness and related properties of real-valued functions.

Complex analysis[edit]

Complex analysis, traditionally known as the theory of functions of a complex variable, is the branch of mathematical analysis that investigates functions of complex numbers.[15] It is useful in many branches of mathematics, including algebraic geometry, number theory, applied mathematics; as well as in physics, including hydrodynamics, thermodynamics, mechanical engineering, electrical engineering, and particularly, quantum field theory.

Complex analysis is particularly concerned with the analytic functions of complex variables (or, more generally, meromorphic functions). Because the separate real and imaginary parts of any analytic function must satisfy Laplace's equation, complex analysis is widely applicable to two-dimensional problems in physics.

Functional analysis[edit]

Functional analysis is a branch of mathematical analysis, the core of which is formed by the study of vector spaces endowed with some kind of limit-related structure (e.g. inner product, norm, topology, etc.) and the linear operators acting upon these spaces and respecting these structures in a suitable sense.[16][17] The historical roots of functional analysis lie in the study of spaces of functions and the formulation of properties of transformations of functions such as the Fourier transform as transformations defining continuous, unitary etc. operators between function spaces. This point of view turned out to be particularly useful for the study of differential and integral equations.

Differential equations[edit]

A differential equation is a mathematicalequation for an unknown function of one or several variables that relates the values of the function itself and its derivatives of various orders.[18][19][20] Differential equations play a prominent role in engineering, physics, economics, biology, and other disciplines.

Differential equations arise in many areas of science and technology, specifically whenever a deterministic relation involving some continuously varying quantities (modeled by functions) and their rates of change in space or time (expressed as derivatives) is known or postulated. This is illustrated in classical mechanics, where the motion of a body is described by its position and velocity as the time value varies. Newton's laws allow one (given the position, velocity, acceleration and various forces acting on the body) to express these variables dynamically as a differential equation for the unknown position of the body as a function of time. In some cases, this differential equation (called an equation of motion) may be solved explicitly.

Measure theory[edit]

A measure on a set is a systematic way to assign a number to each suitable subset of that set, intuitively interpreted as its size.[21] In this sense, a measure is a generalization of the concepts of length, area, and volume. A particularly important example is the Lebesgue measure on a Euclidean space, which assigns the conventional length, area, and volume of Euclidean geometry to suitable subsets of the n{displaystyle n}-dimensional Euclidean space Rn{displaystyle mathbb {R} ^{n}}. For instance, the Lebesgue measure of the interval[0,1]{displaystyle left[0,1right]} in the real numbers is its length in the everyday sense of the word – specifically, 1.

Technically, a measure is a function that assigns a non-negative real number or +∞ to (certain) subsets of a set X{displaystyle X}. It must assign 0 to the empty set and be (countably) additive: the measure of a 'large' subset that can be decomposed into a finite (or countable) number of 'smaller' disjoint subsets, is the sum of the measures of the 'smaller' subsets. In general, if one wants to associate a consistent size to each subset of a given set while satisfying the other axioms of a measure, one only finds trivial examples like the counting measure. This problem was resolved by defining measure only on a sub-collection of all subsets; the so-called measurable subsets, which are required to form a σ{displaystyle sigma }-algebra. This means that countable unions, countable intersections and complements of measurable subsets are measurable. Non-measurable sets in a Euclidean space, on which the Lebesgue measure cannot be defined consistently, are necessarily complicated in the sense of being badly mixed up with their complement. Indeed, their existence is a non-trivial consequence of the axiom of choice.

Numerical analysis[edit]

Numerical analysis is the study of algorithms that use numerical approximation (as opposed to general symbolic manipulations) for the problems of mathematical analysis (as distinguished from discrete mathematics).[22]

Modern numerical analysis does not seek exact answers, because exact answers are often impossible to obtain in practice. Instead, much of numerical analysis is concerned with obtaining approximate solutions while maintaining reasonable bounds on errors.

Numerical analysis naturally finds applications in all fields of engineering and the physical sciences, but in the 21st century, the life sciences and even the arts have adopted elements of scientific computations. Ordinary differential equations appear in celestial mechanics (planets, stars and galaxies); numerical linear algebra is important for data analysis; stochastic differential equations and Markov chains are essential in simulating living cells for medicine and biology.

Other topics[edit]

  • Calculus of variations deals with extremizing functionals, as opposed to ordinary calculus which deals with functions.
  • Harmonic analysis deals with the representation of functions or signals as the superposition of basic waves.
  • Geometric analysis involves the use of geometrical methods in the study of partial differential equations and the application of the theory of partial differential equations to geometry.
  • Clifford analysis, the study of Clifford valued functions that are annihilated by Dirac or Dirac-like operators, termed in general as monogenic or Clifford analytic functions.
  • p-adic analysis, the study of analysis within the context of p-adic numbers, which differs in some interesting and surprising ways from its real and complex counterparts.
  • Non-standard analysis, which investigates the hyperreal numbers and their functions and gives a rigorous treatment of infinitesimals and infinitely large numbers.
  • Computable analysis, the study of which parts of analysis can be carried out in a computable manner.
  • Stochastic calculus – analytical notions developed for stochastic processes.
  • Set-valued analysis – applies ideas from analysis and topology to set-valued functions.
  • Convex analysis, the study of convex sets and functions.
  • Idempotent analysis – analysis in the context of an idempotent semiring, where the lack of an additive inverse is compensated somewhat by the idempotent rule A + A = A.
    • Tropical analysis – analysis of the idempotent semiring called the tropical semiring (or max-plus algebra/min-plus algebra).
  • Non-Newtonian calculus, alternatives to the classical calculus of Newton and Leibniz.

Applications[edit]

Techniques from analysis are also found in other areas such as:

Physical sciences[edit]

The vast majority of classical mechanics, relativity, and quantum mechanics is based on applied analysis, and differential equations in particular. Examples of important differential equations include Newton's second law, the Schrödinger equation, and the Einstein field equations.

Functional analysis is also a major factor in quantum mechanics.

Signal processing[edit]

When processing signals, such as audio, radio waves, light waves, seismic waves, and even images, Fourier analysis can isolate individual components of a compound waveform, concentrating them for easier detection or removal. A large family of signal processing techniques consist of Fourier-transforming a signal, manipulating the Fourier-transformed data in a simple way, and reversing the transformation.[23]

Other areas of mathematics[edit]

Techniques from analysis are used in many areas of mathematics, including:

  • Differential entropy in information theory
  • Differential geometry, the application of calculus to specific mathematical spaces known as manifolds that possess a complicated internal structure but behave in a simple manner locally.

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^Edwin Hewitt and Karl Stromberg, 'Real and Abstract Analysis', Springer-Verlag, 1965
  2. ^Stillwell, John Colin. 'analysis mathematics'. Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 2015-07-31.
  3. ^ abJahnke, Hans Niels (2003). A History of Analysis. American Mathematical Society. p. 7. ISBN978-0-8218-2623-2.
  4. ^Stillwell (2004). 'Infinite Series'. Mathematics and its History (2nd ed.). Springer Science + Business Media Inc. p. 170. ISBN978-0-387-95336-6. Infinite series were present in Greek mathematics, [..] There is no question that Zeno's paradox of the dichotomy (Section 4.1), for example, concerns the decomposition of the number 1 into the infinite series 12 + 122 + 123 + 124 + .. and that Archimedes found the area of the parabolic segment (Section 4.4) essentially by summing the infinite series 1 + 14 + 142 + 143 + .. = 43. Both these examples are special cases of the result we express as summation of a geometric series
  5. ^Smith 1958.
  6. ^Pinto, J. Sousa (2004). Infinitesimal Methods of Mathematical Analysis. Horwood Publishing. p. 8. ISBN978-1-898563-99-0.
  7. ^Dun, Liu; Fan, Dainian; Cohen, Robert Sonné (1966). A comparison of Archimedes' and Liu Hui's studies of circles. Chinese studies in the history and philosophy of science and technology. 130. Springer. p. 279. ISBN978-0-7923-3463-7., Chapter, p. 279
  8. ^Zill, Dennis G.; Wright, Scott; Wright, Warren S. (2009). Calculus: Early Transcendentals (3 ed.). Jones & Bartlett Learning. p. xxvii. ISBN978-0-7637-5995-7.
  9. ^Seal, Sir Brajendranath (1915), 'The positive sciences of the ancient Hindus', Nature, 97 (2426): 177, Bibcode:1916Natur.97.177., doi:10.1038/097177a0, hdl:2027/mdp.39015004845684
  10. ^Rajagopal, C.T.; Rangachari, M.S. (June 1978). 'On an untapped source of medieval Keralese Mathematics'. Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 18 (2): 89–102. doi:10.1007/BF00348142 (inactive 2019-08-18).
  11. ^Dunham, William (1999). Euler: The Master of Us All. The Mathematical Association of America. p. 17.
  12. ^*Cooke, Roger (1997). 'Beyond the Calculus'. The History of Mathematics: A Brief Course. Wiley-Interscience. p. 379. ISBN978-0-471-18082-1. Real analysis began its growth as an independent subject with the introduction of the modern definition of continuity in 1816 by the Czech mathematician Bernard Bolzano (1781–1848)
  13. ^Rudin, Walter. Principles of Mathematical Analysis. Walter Rudin Student Series in Advanced Mathematics (3rd ed.). McGraw–Hill. ISBN978-0-07-054235-8.
  14. ^Abbott, Stephen (2001). Understanding Analysis. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics. New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN978-0-387-95060-0.
  15. ^Ahlfors, L. (1979). Complex Analysis (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN978-0-07-000657-7.
  16. ^Rudin, Walter (1991). Functional Analysis. McGraw-Hill Science. ISBN978-0-07-054236-5.
  17. ^Conway, J. B. (1994). A Course in Functional Analysis (2nd ed.). Springer-Verlag. ISBN978-0-387-97245-9.
  18. ^Ince, Edward L. (1956). Ordinary Differential Equations. Dover Publications. ISBN978-0-486-60349-0.
  19. ^Witold Hurewicz, Lectures on Ordinary Differential Equations, Dover Publications, ISBN0-486-49510-8
  20. ^Evans, L.C. (1998), Partial Differential Equations, Providence: American Mathematical Society, ISBN978-0-8218-0772-9
  21. ^Tao, Terence (2011). An Introduction to Measure Theory. American Mathematical Society. ISBN978-0-8218-6919-2.
  22. ^Hildebrand, F.B. (1974). Introduction to Numerical Analysis (2nd ed.). McGraw-Hill. ISBN978-0-07-028761-7.
  23. ^Rabiner, L.R.; Gold, B. (1975). Theory and Application of Digital Signal Processing. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. ISBN978-0-13-914101-0.

References[edit]

  • Aleksandrov, A.D.; Kolmogorov, A.N.; Lavrent'ev, M.A., eds. (1984). Mathematics, its Content, Methods, and Meaning. Translated by Gould, S.H.; Hirsch, K.A.; Bartha, T. Translation edited by S.H. Gould (2nd ed.). MIT Press; published in cooperation with the American Mathematical Society.
  • Apostol, Tom M. (1974). Mathematical Analysis (2nd ed.). Addison–Wesley. ISBN978-0-201-00288-1.
  • Binmore, K.G. (1980–1981). The foundations of analysis: a straightforward introduction. Cambridge University Press.
  • Johnsonbaugh, Richard; Pfaffenberger, W.E. (1981). Foundations of mathematical analysis. New York: M. Dekker.
  • Nikol'skii, S.M. (2002). 'Mathematical analysis'. In Hazewinkel, Michiel (ed.). Encyclopaedia of Mathematics. Springer-Verlag. ISBN978-1-4020-0609-8. Archived from the original on 9 April 2006.
  • Nicola Fusco, Paolo Marcellini, Carlo Sbordone (1996). Analisi Matematica Due (in Italian). Liguori Editore. ISBN978-88-207-2675-1.CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  • Rombaldi, Jean-Étienne (2004). Éléments d'analyse réelle : CAPES et agrégation interne de mathématiques (in French). EDP Sciences. ISBN978-2-86883-681-6.
  • Rudin, Walter (1976). Principles of Mathematical Analysis (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN978-0-07-054235-8.
  • Rudin, Walter (1987). Real and Complex Analysis (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN978-0-07-054234-1.
  • Smith, David E. (1958). History of Mathematics. Dover Publications. ISBN978-0-486-20430-7.
  • Whittaker, E.T.; Watson, G N. (1927). A Course of Modern Analysis (4th ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0-521-58807-2.
  • 'Real Analysis - Course Notes'(PDF).

External links[edit]

Wikiquote has quotations related to: Mathematical analysis
Wikimedia Commons has media related to Mathematical analysis.
  • Basic Analysis: Introduction to Real Analysis by Jiri Lebl (Creative Commons BY-NC-SA)
Retrieved from 'https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Mathematical_analysis&oldid=917401887'
The first four partial sums of the Fourier series for a square wave. Fourier series are an important tool in real analysis.

In mathematics, real analysis is the branch of mathematical analysis that studies the behavior of real numbers, sequences and series of real numbers, and real-valued functions.[1] Some particular properties of real-valued sequences and functions that real analysis studies include convergence, limits, continuity, smoothness, differentiability and integrability.

Real analysis is distinguished from complex analysis, which deals with the study of complex numbers and their functions.

  • 1Scope
    • 1.5Limits and convergence
    • 1.7Continuity
    • 1.9Series
    • 1.10Integration

Scope[edit]

Construction of the real numbers[edit]

The theorems of real analysis rely intimately upon the structure of the real number line. The real number system consists of a set (R{displaystyle mathbb {R} }), together with two binary operations denoted + and , and an order denoted <. The operations make the real numbers a field, and, along with the order, an ordered field. The real number system is the unique complete ordered field, in the sense that any other complete ordered field is isomorphic to it. Intuitively, completeness means that there are no 'gaps' in the real numbers. In particular, this property distinguishes the real numbers from other ordered fields (e.g., the rational numbers Q{displaystyle mathbb {Q} }) and is critical to the proof of several key properties of functions of the real numbers. The completeness of the reals is often conveniently expressed as the least upper bound property (see below).

There are several ways of formalizing the definition of the real numbers. Modern approaches consist of providing a list of axioms, and a proof of the existence of a model for them, which has above properties. Moreover, one may show that any two models are isomorphic, which means that all models have exactly the same properties, and that one may forget how the model is constructed for using real numbers. Some of these constructions are described in the main article.

Order properties of the real numbers[edit]

The real numbers have several important lattice-theoretic properties that are absent in the complex numbers. Most importantly, the real numbers form an ordered field, in which sums and products of positive numbers are also positive. Moreover, the ordering of the real numbers is total, and the real numbers have the least upper bound property:

Every nonempty subset of R{displaystyle mathbb {R} } that has an upper bound has a least upper bound that is also a real number.

These order-theoretic properties lead to a number of important results in real analysis, such as the monotone convergence theorem, the intermediate value theorem and the mean value theorem.

However, while the results in real analysis are stated for real numbers, many of these results can be generalized to other mathematical objects. In particular, many ideas in functional analysis and operator theory generalize properties of the real numbers – such generalizations include the theories of Riesz spaces and positive operators. Also, mathematicians consider real and imaginary parts of complex sequences, or by pointwise evaluation of operator sequences.

Topological properties of the real numbers[edit]

Many of the theorems of real analysis are consequences of the topological properties of the real number line. The order properties of the real numbers described above are closely related to these topological properties. As a topological space, the real numbers has a standard topology, which is the order topology induced by order <{displaystyle <}. Alternatively, by defining the metric or distance functiond:R×RR0{displaystyle d:mathbb {R} times mathbb {R} to mathbb {R} _{geq 0}} using the absolute value function as d(x,y)=xy{displaystyle d(x,y)= x-y }, the real numbers become the prototypical example of a metric space. The topology induced by metric d{displaystyle d} turns out to be identical to the standard topology induced by order <{displaystyle <}. Theorems like the intermediate value theorem that are essentially topological in nature can often be proved in the more general setting of metric or topological spaces rather than in R{displaystyle mathbb {R} } only. Often, such proofs tend to be shorter or simpler compared to classical proofs that apply direct methods.

Sequences[edit]

A sequence is a function whose domain is a countable, totally ordered set. The domain is usually taken to be the natural numbers[2], although it is occasionally convenient to also consider bidirectional sequences indexed by the set of all integers, including negative indices.

Of interest in real analysis, a real-valued sequence, here indexed by the natural numbers, is a map a:NR,nan{displaystyle a:mathbb {N} to mathbb {R} , nmapsto a_{n}}. Each a(n)=an{displaystyle a(n)=a_{n}} is referred to as a term (or, less commonly, an element) of the sequence. A sequence is rarely denoted explicitly as a function; instead, by convention, it is almost always notated as if it were an ordered ∞-tuple, with individual terms or a general term enclosed in parentheses:

(an)=(an)nN=(a1,a2,a3,){displaystyle (a_{n})=(a_{n})_{nin mathbb {N} }=(a_{1},a_{2},a_{3},cdots )}.[3]

A sequence that tends to a limit (i.e., limnan{textstyle lim _{nto infty }a_{n}} exists) is said to be convergent; otherwise it is divergent. (See the section on limits and convergence for details.) A real-valued sequence (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} is bounded if there exists MR{displaystyle Min mathbb {R} } such that an<M{displaystyle a_{n} <M} for all nN{displaystyle nin mathbb {N} }. A real-valued sequence (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} is monotonically increasing or decreasing if

a1a2a3{displaystyle a_{1}leq a_{2}leq a_{3}leq ldots } or a1a2a3{displaystyle a_{1}geq a_{2}geq a_{3}geq ldots }

holds, respectively. If either holds, the sequence is said to be monotonic. The monotonicity is strict if the chained inequalities still hold with {displaystyle leq } or {displaystyle geq } replaced by < or >.

Given a sequence (an){displaystyle (a_{n})}, another sequence (bk){displaystyle (b_{k})} is a subsequence of (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} if bk=ank{displaystyle b_{k}=a_{n_{k}}} for all positive integers k{displaystyle k} and (nk){displaystyle (n_{k})} is a strictly increasing sequence of natural numbers.

Limits and convergence[edit]

Roughly speaking, a limit is the value that a function or a sequence 'approaches' as the input or index approaches some value.[4] (This value can include the symbols ±{displaystyle pm infty } when addressing the behavior of a function or sequence as the variable increases or decreases without bound.) The idea of a limit is fundamental to calculus (and mathematical analysis in general) and its formal definition is used in turn to define notions like continuity, derivatives, and integrals. (In fact, the study of limiting behavior has been used as a characteristic that distinguishes calculus and mathematical analysis from other branches of mathematics.)

The concept of limit was informally introduced for functions by Newton and Leibniz, at the end of 17th century, for building infinitesimal calculus. For sequences, the concept was introduced by Cauchy, and made rigorous, at the end of 19th century by Bolzano and Weierstrass, who gave the modern ε-δ definition, which follows.

Definition. Let f{displaystyle f} be a real-valued function defined on ER{displaystyle Esubset mathbb {R} }. We say that f(x){displaystyle f(x)} tends to L{displaystyle L} as x{displaystyle x} approaches x0{displaystyle x_{0}}, or that the limit of f(x){displaystyle f(x)} as x{displaystyle x} approaches x0{displaystyle x_{0}} is L{displaystyle L} if, for any ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0}, there exists δ>0{displaystyle delta >0} such that for all xE{displaystyle xin E}, 0<xx0<δ{displaystyle 0< x-x_{0} <delta } implies that f(x)L<ϵ{displaystyle f(x)-L <epsilon }. We write this symbolically as

f(x)Lasxx0{displaystyle f(x)to L {text{as}} xto x_{0}}, or limxx0f(x)=L{displaystyle lim _{xto x_{0}}f(x)=L}.

Intuitively, this definition can be thought of in the following way: We say that f(x)L{displaystyle f(x)to L} as xx0{displaystyle xto x_{0}}, when, given any positive number ϵ{displaystyle epsilon }, no matter how small, we can always find a δ{displaystyle delta }, such that we can guarantee that f(x){displaystyle f(x)} and L{displaystyle L} are less than ϵ{displaystyle epsilon } apart, as long as x{displaystyle x} (in the domain of f{displaystyle f}) is a real number that is less than δ{displaystyle delta } away from x0{displaystyle x_{0}} but distinct from x0{displaystyle x_{0}}. The purpose of the last stipulation, which corresponds to the condition 0<xx0{displaystyle 0< x-x_{0} } in the definition, is to ensure that limxx0f(x)=L{displaystyle lim _{xto x_{0}}f(x)=L} does not imply anything about the value of f(x0){displaystyle f(x_{0})} itself. Actually, x0{displaystyle x_{0}} does not even need to be in the domain of f{displaystyle f} in order for limxx0f(x){displaystyle lim _{xto x_{0}}f(x)} to exist.

In a slightly different but related context, the concept of a limit applies to the behavior of a sequence (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} when n{displaystyle n} becomes large.

Definition. Let (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} be a real-valued sequence. We say that (an){displaystyle (a_{n})}converges toa{displaystyle a} if, for any ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0}, there exists a natural number N{displaystyle N} such that nN{displaystyle ngeq N} implies that aan<ϵ{displaystyle a-a_{n} <epsilon }. We write this symbolically as

anaasn{displaystyle a_{n}to a {text{as}} nto infty }, or limnan=a{displaystyle lim _{nto infty }a_{n}=a};

if (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} fails to converge, we say that (an){displaystyle (a_{n})}diverges.

Generalizing to a real-valued function of a real variable, a slight modification of this definition (replacement of sequence (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} and term an{displaystyle a_{n}} by function f{displaystyle f} and value f(x){displaystyle f(x)} and natural numbers N{displaystyle N} and n{displaystyle n} by real numbers M{displaystyle M} and x{displaystyle x}, respectively) yields the definition of the limit of f(x){displaystyle f(x)} as x{displaystyle x} increases without bound, notated limxf(x){displaystyle lim _{xto infty }f(x)}. Reversing the inequality xM{displaystyle xgeq M} to xM{displaystyle xleq M} gives the corresponding definition of the limit of f(x){displaystyle f(x)} as x{displaystyle x}decreaseswithout bound, limxf(x){displaystyle lim _{xto -infty }f(x)}.

Sometimes, it is useful to conclude that a sequence converges, even though the value to which it converges is unknown or irrelevant. In these cases, the concept of a Cauchy sequence is useful.

Definition. Let (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} be a real-valued sequence. We say that (an){displaystyle (a_{n})} is a Cauchy sequence if, for any ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0}, there exists a natural number N{displaystyle N} such that m,nN{displaystyle m,ngeq N} implies that aman<ϵ{displaystyle a_{m}-a_{n} <epsilon }.

It can be shown that a real-valued sequence is Cauchy if and only if it is convergent. This property of the real numbers is expressed by saying that the real numbers endowed with the standard metric, (R,){displaystyle (mathbb {R} , cdot )}, is a complete metric space. In a general metric space, however, a Cauchy sequence need not converge.

In addition, for real-valued sequences that are monotonic, it can be shown that the sequence is bounded if and only if it is convergent.

Uniform and pointwise convergence for sequences of functions[edit]

In addition to sequences of numbers, one may also speak of sequences of functionsonER{displaystyle Esubset mathbb {R} }, that is, infinite, ordered families of functions fn:ER{displaystyle f_{n}:Eto mathbb {R} }, denoted (fn)n=1{displaystyle (f_{n})_{n=1}^{infty }}, and their convergence properties. However, in the case of sequences of functions, there are two kinds of convergence, known as pointwise convergence and uniform convergence, that need to be distinguished.

Roughly speaking, pointwise convergence of functions fn{displaystyle f_{n}} to a limiting function f:ER{displaystyle f:Eto mathbb {R} }, denoted fnf{displaystyle f_{n}rightarrow f}, simply means that given any xE{displaystyle xin E}, fn(x)f(x){displaystyle f_{n}(x)to f(x)} as n{displaystyle nto infty }. In contrast, uniform convergence is a stronger type of convergence, in the sense that a uniformly convergent sequence of functions also converges pointwise, but not conversely. Uniform convergence requires members of the family of functions, fn{displaystyle f_{n}}, to fall within some error ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0} of f{displaystyle f} for every value of xE{displaystyle xin E}, whenever nN{displaystyle ngeq N}, for some integer N{displaystyle N}. For a family of functions to uniformly converge, sometimes denoted fnf{displaystyle f_{n}rightrightarrows f}, such a value of N{displaystyle N} must exist for any ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0} given, no matter how small. Intuitively, we can visualize this situation by imagining that, for a large enough N{displaystyle N}, the functions fN,fN+1,fN+2,{displaystyle f_{N},f_{N+1},f_{N+2},ldots } are all confined within a 'tube' of width 2ϵ{displaystyle 2epsilon } about f{displaystyle f} (i.e., between fϵ{displaystyle f-epsilon } and f+ϵ{displaystyle f+epsilon }) for every value in their domainE{displaystyle E}.

The distinction between pointwise and uniform convergence is important when exchanging the order of two limiting operations (e.g., taking a limit, a derivative, or integral) is desired: in order for the exchange to be well-behaved, many theorems of real analysis call for uniform convergence. For example, a sequence of continuous functions (see below) is guaranteed to converge to a continuous limiting function if the convergence is uniform, while the limiting function may not be continuous if convergence is only pointwise. Karl Weierstrass is generally credited for clearly defining the concept of uniform convergence and fully investigating its implications.

Compactness[edit]

Compactness is a concept from general topology that plays an important role in many of the theorems of real analysis. The property of compactness is a generalization of the notion of a set being closed and bounded. (In the context of real analysis, these notions are equivalent: a set in Euclidean space is compact if and only if it is closed and bounded.) Briefly, a closed set contains all of its boundary points, while a set is bounded if there exists a real number such that the distance between any two points of the set is less than that number. In R{displaystyle mathbb {R} }, sets that are closed and bounded, and therefore compact, include the empty set, any finite number of points, closed intervals, and their finite unions. However, this list is not exhaustive; for instance, the set {1/n:nN}{0}{displaystyle {1/n:nin mathbb {N} }cup {0}} is another example of a compact set. On the other hand, the set {1/n:nN}{displaystyle {1/n:nin mathbb {N} }} is not compact because it is bounded but not closed, as the boundary point 0 is not a member of the set. The set [0,){displaystyle [0,infty )} is also not compact because it is closed but not bounded.

For subsets of the real numbers, there are several equivalent definitions of compactness.

Definition. A set ER{displaystyle Esubset mathbb {R} } is compact if it is closed and bounded.

This definition also holds for Euclidean space of any finite dimension, Rn{displaystyle mathbb {R} ^{n}}, but it is not valid for metric spaces in general. The equivalence of the definition with the definition of compactness based on subcovers, given later in this section, is known as the Heine-Borel theorem.

A more general definition that applies to all metric spaces uses the notion of a subsequence (see above).

Definition. A set E{displaystyle E} in a metric space is compact if every sequence in E{displaystyle E} has a convergent subsequence.

This particular property is known as subsequential compactness. In R{displaystyle mathbb {R} }, a set is subsequentially compact if and only if it is closed and bounded, making this definition equivalent to the one given above. Subsequential compactness is equivalent to the definition of compactness based on subcovers for metric spaces, but not for topological spaces in general.

The most general definition of compactness relies on the notion of open covers and subcovers, which is applicable to topological spaces (and thus to metric spaces and R{displaystyle mathbb {R} } as special cases). In brief, a collection of open sets Uα{displaystyle U_{alpha }} is said to be an open cover of set X{displaystyle X} if the union of these sets is a superset of X{displaystyle X}. This open cover is said to have a finite subcover if a finite subcollection of the Uα{displaystyle U_{alpha }} could be found that also covers X{displaystyle X}.

Definition. A set X{displaystyle X} in a topological space is compact if every open cover of X{displaystyle X} has a finite subcover.

Compact sets are well-behaved with respect to properties like convergence and continuity. For instance, any Cauchy sequence in a compact metric space is convergent. As another example, the image of a compact metric space under a continuous map is also compact.

Continuity[edit]

A function from the set of real numbers to the real numbers can be represented by a graph in the Cartesian plane; such a function is continuous if, roughly speaking, the graph is a single unbroken curve with no 'holes' or 'jumps'.

There are several ways to make this intuition mathematically rigorous. Several definitions of varying levels of generality can be given. In cases where two or more definitions are applicable, they are readily shown to be equivalent to one another, so the most convenient definition can be used to determine whether a given function is continuous or not. In the first definition given below, f:IR{displaystyle f:Ito mathbb {R} } is a function defined on a non-degenerate interval I{displaystyle I} of the set of real numbers as its domain. Some possibilities include I=R{displaystyle I=mathbb {R} }, the whole set of real numbers, an open intervalI=(a,b)={xRa<x<b},{displaystyle I=(a,b)={xin mathbb {R} , ,a<x<b},} or a closed intervalI=[a,b]={xRaxb}.{displaystyle I=[a,b]={xin mathbb {R} , ,aleq xleq b}.} Here, a{displaystyle a} and b{displaystyle b} are distinct real numbers, and we exclude the case of I{displaystyle I} being empty or consisting of only one point, in particular.

Definition. If IR{displaystyle Isubset mathbb {R} } is a non-degenerate interval, we say that f:IR{displaystyle f:Ito mathbb {R} } is continuous atpE{displaystyle pin E} if limxpf(x)=f(p){displaystyle lim _{xto p}f(x)=f(p)}. We say that f{displaystyle f} is a continuous map if f{displaystyle f} is continuous at every pI{displaystyle pin I}.

In contrast to the requirements for f{displaystyle f} to have a limit at a point p{displaystyle p}, which do not constrain the behavior of f{displaystyle f} at p{displaystyle p} itself, the following two conditions, in addition to the existence of limxpf(x){textstyle lim _{xto p}f(x)}, must also hold in order for f{displaystyle f} to be continuous at p{displaystyle p}: (i)f{displaystyle f} must be defined at p{displaystyle p}, i.e., p{displaystyle p} is in the domain of f{displaystyle f}; and(ii)f(x)f(p){displaystyle f(x)to f(p)} as xp{displaystyle xto p}. The definition above actually applies to any domain E{displaystyle E} that does not contain an isolated point, or equivalently, E{displaystyle E} where every pE{displaystyle pin E} is a limit point of E{displaystyle E}. A more general definition applying to f:XR{displaystyle f:Xto mathbb {R} } with a general domain XR{displaystyle Xsubset mathbb {R} } is the following:

Definition. If X{displaystyle X} is an arbitrary subset of R{displaystyle mathbb {R} }, we say that f:XR{displaystyle f:Xto mathbb {R} } is continuous atpX{displaystyle pin X} if, for any ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0}, there exists δ>0{displaystyle delta >0} such that for all xX{displaystyle xin X}, xp<δ{displaystyle x-p <delta } implies that f(x)f(p)<ϵ{displaystyle f(x)-f(p) <epsilon }. We say that f{displaystyle f} is a continuous map if f{displaystyle f} is continuous at every pX{displaystyle pin X}.

A consequence of this definition is that f{displaystyle f} is trivially continuous at any isolated pointpX{displaystyle pin X}. This somewhat unintuitive treatment of isolated points is necessary to ensure that our definition of continuity for functions on the real line is consistent with the most general definition of continuity for maps between topological spaces (which includes metric spaces and R{displaystyle mathbb {R} } in particular as special cases). This definition, which extends beyond the scope of our discussion of real analysis, is given below for completeness.

Classic traveller pdf

Definition. If X{displaystyle X} and Y{displaystyle Y} are topological spaces, we say that f:XY{displaystyle f:Xto Y} is continuous atpX{displaystyle pin X} if f1(V){displaystyle f^{-1}(V)} is a neighborhood of p{displaystyle p} in X{displaystyle X} for every neighborhood V{displaystyle V} of f(p){displaystyle f(p)} in Y{displaystyle Y}. We say that f{displaystyle f} is a continuous map if f1(U){displaystyle f^{-1}(U)} is open in X{displaystyle X} for every U{displaystyle U} open in Y{displaystyle Y}.

(Here, f1(S){displaystyle f^{-1}(S)} refers to the preimage of SY{displaystyle Ssubset Y} under f{displaystyle f}.)

Uniform continuity[edit]

Definition. If X{displaystyle X} is a subset of the real numbers, we say a function f:XR{displaystyle f:Xto mathbb {R} } is uniformly continuousonX{displaystyle X} if, for any ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0}, there exists a δ>0{displaystyle delta >0} such that for all x,yX{displaystyle x,yin X}, xy<δ{displaystyle x-y <delta } implies that f(x)f(y)<ϵ{displaystyle f(x)-f(y) <epsilon }.

Explicitly, when a function is uniformly continuous on X{displaystyle X}, the choice of δ{displaystyle delta } needed to fulfill the definition must work for all ofX{displaystyle X} for a given ϵ{displaystyle epsilon }. In contrast, when a function is continuous at every point pX{displaystyle pin X} (or said to be continuous on X{displaystyle X}), the choice of δ{displaystyle delta } may depend on both ϵ{displaystyle epsilon }andp{displaystyle p}. Importantly, in contrast to simple continuity, uniform continuity is a property of a function that only makes sense with a specified domain; to speak of uniform continuity at a single point p{displaystyle p} is meaningless.

On a compact set, it is easily shown that all continuous functions are uniformly continuous. If E{displaystyle E} is a bounded noncompact subset of R{displaystyle mathbb {R} }, then there exists f:ER{displaystyle f:Eto mathbb {R} } that is continuous but not uniformly continuous. As a simple example, consider f:(0,1)R{displaystyle f:(0,1)to mathbb {R} } defined by f(x)=1/x{displaystyle f(x)=1/x}. By choosing points close to 0, we can always make f(x)f(y)>ϵ{displaystyle f(x)-f(y) >epsilon } for any single choice of δ>0{displaystyle delta >0}, for a given ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0}.

Absolute continuity[edit]

Definition. Let IR{displaystyle Isubset mathbb {R} } be an interval on the real line. A function f:IR{displaystyle f:Ito mathbb {R} } is said to be absolutely continuousonI{displaystyle I} if for every positive number ϵ{displaystyle epsilon }, there is a positive number δ{displaystyle delta } such that whenever a finite sequence of pairwise disjoint sub-intervals (x1,y1),(x2,y2),,(xn,yn){displaystyle (x_{1},y_{1}),(x_{2},y_{2}),ldots ,(x_{n},y_{n})} of I{displaystyle I} satisfies[5]

k=1n(ykxk)<δ{displaystyle sum _{k=1}^{n}(y_{k}-x_{k})<delta }

then

k=1nf(yk)f(xk)<ϵ.{displaystyle displaystyle sum _{k=1}^{n} f(y_{k})-f(x_{k}) <epsilon .}

Absolutely continuous functions are continuous: consider the case n = 1 in this definition. The collection of all absolutely continuous functions on I is denoted AC(I). Absolute continuity is an important concept in the Lebesgue theory of integration, allowing the formulation of a generalized version of the fundamental theorem of calculus that applies to the Lebesgue integral.

Differentiation[edit]

The notion of the derivative of a function or differentiability originates from the concept of approximating a function near a given point using the 'best' linear approximation. This approximation, if it exists, is unique and is given by the line that is tangent to the function at the given point a{displaystyle a}, and the slope of the line is the derivative of the function at a{displaystyle a}.

A function f:RR{displaystyle f:mathbb {R} to mathbb {R} } is differentiable at a{displaystyle a} if the limit

f(a)=limh0f(a+h)f(a)h{displaystyle f'(a)=lim _{hto 0}{frac {f(a+h)-f(a)}{h}}}

exists. This limit is known as the derivative of f{displaystyle f} at a{displaystyle a}, and the function f{displaystyle f'}, possibly defined on only a subset of R{displaystyle mathbb {R} }, is the derivative (or derivative function) off{displaystyle f}. If the derivative exists everywhere, the function is said to be differentiable.

As a simple consequence of the definition, f{displaystyle f} is continuous at a{displaystyle a} if it is differentiable there. Differentiability is therefore a stronger regularity condition (condition describing the 'smoothness' of a function) than continuity, and it is possible for a function to be continuous on the entire real line but not differentiable anywhere (see Weierstrass's nowhere differentiable continuous function). It is possible to discuss the existence of higher-order derivatives as well, by finding the derivative of a derivative function, and so on.

One can classify functions by their differentiability class. The class C0{displaystyle C^{0}} (sometimes C0([a,b]){displaystyle C^{0}([a,b])} to indicate the interval of applicability) consists of all continuous functions. The class C1{displaystyle C^{1}} consists of all differentiable functions whose derivative is continuous; such functions are called continuously differentiable. Thus, a C1{displaystyle C^{1}} function is exactly a function whose derivative exists and is of class C0{displaystyle C^{0}}. In general, the classes Ck{displaystyle C^{k}} can be defined recursively by declaring C0{displaystyle C^{0}} to be the set of all continuous functions and declaring Ck{displaystyle C^{k}} for any positive integer k{displaystyle k} to be the set of all differentiable functions whose derivative is in Ck1{displaystyle C^{k-1}}. In particular, Ck{displaystyle C^{k}} is contained in Ck1{displaystyle C^{k-1}} for every k{displaystyle k}, and there are examples to show that this containment is strict. Class C{displaystyle C^{infty }} is the intersection of the sets Ck{displaystyle C^{k}} as k{displaystyle k} varies over the non-negative integers, and the members of this class are known as the smooth functions. Class Cω{displaystyle C^{omega }} consists of all analytic functions, and is strictly contained in C{displaystyle C^{infty }} (see bump function for a smooth function that is not analytic).

The chain rule, mean value theorem, L'Hôpital's rule, and Taylor's theorem are important results in the elementary theory of the derivative.

Series[edit]

A series formalizes the imprecise notion of taking the sum of an endless sequence of numbers. The idea that taking the sum of an 'infinite' number of terms can lead to a finite result was counterintuitive to the ancient Greeks and led to the formulation of a number of paradoxes by Zeno and other philosophers. The modern notion of assigning a value to a series avoids dealing with the ill-defined notion of adding an 'infinite' number of terms. Instead, the finite sum of the first n{displaystyle n} terms of the sequence, known as a partial sum, is considered, and the concept of a limit is applied to the sequence of partial sums as n{displaystyle n} grows without bound. The series is assigned the value of this limit, if it exists.

Given an (infinite) sequence(an){displaystyle (a_{n})}, we can define an associated series as the formal mathematical object a1+a2+a3+=n=1an{textstyle a_{1}+a_{2}+a_{3}+cdots =sum _{n=1}^{infty }a_{n}}, sometimes simply written as an{textstyle sum a_{n}}. The partial sums of a series an{textstyle sum a_{n}} are the numbers sn=j=1naj{textstyle s_{n}=sum _{j=1}^{n}a_{j}}. A series an{textstyle sum a_{n}} is said to be convergent if the sequence consisting of its partial sums, (sn){displaystyle (s_{n})}, is convergent; otherwise it is divergent. The sum of a convergent series is defined as the number s=limnsn{textstyle s=lim _{nto infty }s_{n}}.

It is to be emphasized that the word 'sum' is used here in a metaphorical sense as a shorthand for taking the limit of a sequence of partial sums and should not be interpreted as simply 'adding' an infinite number of terms. For instance, in contrast to the behavior of finite sums, rearranging the terms of an infinite series may result in convergence to a different number (see the article on the Riemann rearrangement theorem for further discussion).

An example of a convergent series is a geometric series which forms the basis of one of Zeno's famous paradoxes:

n=112n=12+14+18+=1{displaystyle sum _{n=1}^{infty }{frac {1}{2^{n}}}={frac {1}{2}}+{frac {1}{4}}+{frac {1}{8}}+cdots =1}.

Real Analysis Mathematics Pdf Example

In contrast, the harmonic series has been known since the Middle Ages to be a divergent series:

n=11n=1+12+13+={displaystyle sum _{n=1}^{infty }{frac {1}{n}}=1+{frac {1}{2}}+{frac {1}{3}}+cdots =infty }.

(Here, '={displaystyle =infty }' is merely a notational convention to indicate that the partial sums of the series grow without bound.)

A series an{textstyle sum a_{n}} is said to converge absolutely if an{textstyle sum a_{n} } is convergent. A convergent series an{textstyle sum a_{n}} for which an{textstyle sum a_{n} } diverges is said to converge conditionally (or nonabsolutely). It is easily shown that absolute convergence of a series implies its convergence. On the other hand, an example of a conditionally convergent series is

n=1(1)n1n=112+1314+=log2{displaystyle sum _{n=1}^{infty }{frac {(-1)^{n-1}}{n}}=1-{frac {1}{2}}+{frac {1}{3}}-{frac {1}{4}}+cdots =log 2}.

Taylor series[edit]

The Taylor series of a real or complex-valued functionƒ(x) that is infinitely differentiable at a real or complex numbera is the power series

f(a)+f(a)1!(xa)+f(a)2!(xa)2+f(3)(a)3!(xa)3+.{displaystyle f(a)+{frac {f'(a)}{1!}}(x-a)+{frac {f'(a)}{2!}}(x-a)^{2}+{frac {f^{(3)}(a)}{3!}}(x-a)^{3}+cdots .}

which can be written in the more compact sigma notation as

n=0f(n)(a)n!(xa)n{displaystyle sum _{n=0}^{infty }{frac {f^{(n)}(a)}{n!}},(x-a)^{n}}

where n! denotes the factorial of n and ƒ (n)(a) denotes the nth derivative of ƒ evaluated at the point a. The derivative of order zero ƒ is defined to be ƒ itself and (xa)0 and 0! are both defined to be 1. In the case that a = 0, the series is also called a Maclaurin series.

A Taylor series of f about point a may diverge, converge at only the point a, converge for all x such that xa<R{displaystyle x-a <R} (the largest such R for which convergence is guaranteed is called the radius of convergence), or converge on the entire real line. Even a converging Taylor series may converge to a value different from the value of the function at that point. If the Taylor series at a point has a nonzero radius of convergence, and sums to the function in the disc of convergence, then the function is analytic. The analytic functions have many fundamental properties. In particular, an analytic function of a real variable extends naturally to a function of a complex variable. It is in this way that the exponential function, the logarithm, the trigonometric functions and their inverses are extended to functions of a complex variable.

Fourier series[edit]

Real Analysis Mathematics Pdf Free

Fourier series decomposes periodic functions or periodic signals into the sum of a (possibly infinite) set of simple oscillating functions, namely sines and cosines (or complex exponentials). The study of Fourier series typically occurs and is handled within the branch mathematics > mathematical analysis > Fourier analysis.

Integration[edit]

Integration is a formalization of the problem of finding the area bound by a curve and the related problems of determining the length of a curve or volume enclosed by a surface. The basic strategy to solving problems of this type was known to the ancient Greeks and Chinese, and was known as the method of exhaustion. Generally speaking, the desired area is bounded from above and below, respectively, by increasingly accurate circumscribing and inscribing polygonal approximations whose exact areas can be computed. By considering approximations consisting of a larger and larger ('infinite') number of smaller and smaller ('infinitesimal') pieces, the area bound by the curve can be deduced, as the upper and lower bounds defined by the approximations converge around a common value.

The spirit of this basic strategy can easily be seen in the definition of the Riemann integral, in which the integral is said to exist if upper and lower Riemann (or Darboux) sums converge to a common value as thinner and thinner rectangular slices ('refinements') are considered. Though the machinery used to define it is much more elaborate compared to the Riemann integral, the Lebesgue integral was defined with similar basic ideas in mind. Compared to the Riemann integral, the more sophisticated Lebesgue integral allows area (or length, volume, etc.; termed a 'measure' in general) to be defined and computed for much more complicated and irregular subsets of Euclidean space, although there still exist 'non-measurable' subsets for which an area cannot be assigned.

Riemann integration[edit]

The Riemann integral is defined in terms of Riemann sums of functions with respect to tagged partitions of an interval. Let [a,b]{displaystyle [a,b]} be a closed interval of the real line; then a tagged partitionP{displaystyle {cal {P}}} of [a,b]{displaystyle [a,b]} is a finite sequence

a=x0t1x1t2x2xn1tnxn=b.{displaystyle a=x_{0}leq t_{1}leq x_{1}leq t_{2}leq x_{2}leq cdots leq x_{n-1}leq t_{n}leq x_{n}=b.,!}

This partitions the interval [a,b]{displaystyle [a,b]} into n{displaystyle n} sub-intervals [xi1,xi]{displaystyle [x_{i-1},x_{i}]} indexed by i=1,,n{displaystyle i=1,ldots ,n}, each of which is 'tagged' with a distinguished point ti[xi1,xi]{displaystyle t_{i}in [x_{i-1},x_{i}]}. For a function f{displaystyle f} bounded on [a,b]{displaystyle [a,b]}, we define the Riemann sum of f{displaystyle f} with respect to tagged partition P{displaystyle {cal {P}}} as

i=1nf(ti)Δi,{displaystyle sum _{i=1}^{n}f(t_{i})Delta _{i},}

where Δi=xixi1{displaystyle Delta _{i}=x_{i}-x_{i-1}} is the width of sub-interval i{displaystyle i}. Thus, each term of the sum is the area of a rectangle with height equal to the function value at the distinguished point of the given sub-interval, and width the same as the sub-interval width. The mesh of such a tagged partition is the width of the largest sub-interval formed by the partition, Δi=maxi=1,,nΔi{displaystyle Delta _{i} =max _{i=1,ldots ,n}Delta _{i}}. We say that the Riemann integral of f{displaystyle f} on [a,b]{displaystyle [a,b]} is S{displaystyle S} if for any ϵ>0{displaystyle epsilon >0} there exists δ>0{displaystyle delta >0} such that, for any tagged partition P{displaystyle {cal {P}}} with mesh Δi<δ{displaystyle Delta _{i} <delta }, we have

Si=1nf(ti)Δi<ϵ.{displaystyle left S-sum _{i=1}^{n}f(t_{i})Delta _{i}right <epsilon .}

This is sometimes denoted Rabf=S{displaystyle {mathcal {R}}int _{a}^{b}f=S}. When the chosen tags give the maximum (respectively, minimum) value of each interval, the Riemann sum is known as the upper (respectively, lower) Darboux sum. A function is Darboux integrable if the upper and lower Darboux sums can be made to be arbitrarily close to each other for a sufficiently small mesh. Although this definition gives the Darboux integral the appearance of being a special case of the Riemann integral, they are, in fact, equivalent, in the sense that a function is Darboux integrable if and only if it is Riemann integrable, and the values of the integrals are equal. In fact, calculus and real analysis textbooks often conflate the two, introducing the definition of the Darboux integral as that of the Riemann integral, due to the slightly easier to apply definition of the former.

The fundamental theorem of calculus asserts that integration and differentiation are inverse operations in a certain sense.

Lebesgue integration and measure[edit]

Lebesgue integration is a mathematical construction that extends the integral to a larger class of functions; it also extends the domains on which these functions can be defined. The concept of a measure, an abstraction of length, area, or volume, is central to the definition of the Lebesgue integral and is important to the study of probability theory. (For a construction of the Lebesgue integral, the main article on Lebesgue integration should be consulted.)

Distributions[edit]

Distributions (or generalized functions) are objects that generalize functions. Distributions make it possible to differentiate functions whose derivatives do not exist in the classical sense. In particular, any locally integrable function has a distributional derivative.

Relation to complex analysis[edit]

Real analysis is an area of analysis that studies concepts such as sequences and their limits, continuity, differentiation, integration and sequences of functions. By definition, real analysis focuses on the real numbers, often including positive and negative infinity to form the extended real line. Real analysis is closely related to complex analysis, which studies broadly the same properties of complex numbers. In complex analysis, it is natural to define differentiation via holomorphic functions, which have a number of useful properties, such as repeated differentiability, expressability as power series, and satisfying the Cauchy integral formula.

In real analysis, it is usually more natural to consider differentiable, smooth, or harmonic functions, which are more widely applicable, but may lack some more powerful properties of holomorphic functions. However, results such as the fundamental theorem of algebra are simpler when expressed in terms of complex numbers.

Techniques from the theory of analytic functions of a complex variable are often used in real analysis – such as evaluation of real integrals by residue calculus.

Important results[edit]

Important results include the Bolzano–Weierstrass and Heine–Borel theorems, the intermediate value theorem and mean value theorem, Taylor's theorem, the fundamental theorem of calculus, the Arzelà-Ascoli theorem, the Stone-Weierstrass theorem, Fatou's lemma, and the monotone convergence and dominated convergence theorems.

Generalizations and related areas of mathematics[edit]

Various ideas from real analysis can be generalized from the real line to broader or more abstract contexts. These generalizations link real analysis to other disciplines and subdisciplines, in many cases playing an important role in their development as distinct areas of mathematics. For instance, generalization of ideas like continuous functions and compactness from real analysis to metric spaces and topological spaces connects real analysis to the field of general topology, while generalization of finite-dimensional Euclidean spaces to infinite-dimensional analogs led to the study of Banach spaces, and Hilbert spaces as topics of importance in functional analysis. Georg Cantor's investigation of sets and sequence of real numbers, mappings between them, and the foundational issues of real analysis gave birth to naive set theory. The study of issues of convergence for sequences of functions eventually gave rise to Fourier analysis as a subdiscipline of mathematical analysis. Investigation of the consequences of generalizing differentiability from functions of a real variable to ones of a complex variable gave rise to the concept of holomorphic functions and the inception of complex analysis as another distinct subdiscipline of analysis. On the other hand, the generalization of integration from the Riemann sense to that of Lebesgue led to the formulation of the concept of abstract measure spaces, a fundamental concept in measure theory. Finally, the generalization of integration from the real line to curves and surfaces in higher dimensional space brought about the study of vector calculus, whose further generalization and formalization played an important role in the evolution of the concepts of differential forms and smooth (differentiable) manifolds in differential geometry and other closely related areas of geometry and topology.

Real Analysis Mathematics Pdf

See also[edit]

Real Analysis Mathematics Pdf Online

  • Time-scale calculus – a unification of real analysis with calculus of finite differences
  • Non-Newtonian calculus, alternatives to the classical calculus of Newton and Leibniz.

References[edit]

Real Analysis Mathematics Pdf Format

  1. ^Tao, Terence (2003). 'Lecture notes for MATH 131AH'(PDF). Course Website for MATH 131AH, Department of Mathematics, UCLA.
  2. ^Gaughan, Edward. '1.1 Sequences and Convergence'. Introduction to Analysis. AMS (2009). ISBN0-8218-4787-2.
  3. ^Some authors (e.g., Rudin 1976) use braces instead and write {an}{displaystyle {a_{n}}}. However, this notation conflicts with the usual notation for a set, which, in contrast to a sequence, disregards the order and the multiplicity of its elements.
  4. ^Stewart, James (2008). Calculus: Early Transcendentals (6th ed.). Brooks/Cole. ISBN0-495-01166-5.
  5. ^Royden 1988, Sect. 5.4, page 108; Nielsen 1997, Definition 15.6 on page 251; Athreya & Lahiri 2006, Definitions 4.4.1, 4.4.2 on pages 128,129. The interval I is assumed to be bounded and closed in the former two books but not the latter book.

Bibliography[edit]

  • Abbott, Stephen (2001). Understanding Analysis. Undergradutate Texts in Mathematics. New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN0-387-95060-5.
  • Aliprantis, Charalambos D.; Burkinshaw, Owen (1998). Principles of real analysis (3rd ed.). Academic. ISBN0-12-050257-7.
  • Bartle, Robert G.; Sherbert, Donald R. (2011). Introduction to Real Analysis (4th ed.). New York: John Wiley and Sons. ISBN978-0-471-43331-6.
  • Bressoud, David (2007). A Radical Approach to Real Analysis. MAA. ISBN0-88385-747-2.
  • Browder, Andrew (1996). Mathematical Analysis: An Introduction. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics. New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN0-387-94614-4.
  • Carothers, Neal L. (2000). Real Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0521497565.
  • Dangello, Frank; Seyfried, Michael (1999). Introductory Real Analysis. Brooks Cole. ISBN978-0-395-95933-6.
  • Kolmogorov, A. N.; Fomin, S. V. (1975). Introductory Real Analysis. Translated by Richard A. Silverman. Dover Publications. ISBN0486612260. Retrieved 2 April 2013.
  • Rudin, Walter (1976). Principles of Mathematical Analysis. Walter Rudin Student Series in Advanced Mathematics (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw–Hill. ISBN978-0-07-054235-8.
  • Rudin, Walter (1987). Real and Complex Analysis (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN978-0-07-054234-1.
  • Spivak, Michael (1994). Calculus (3rd ed.). Houston, Texas: Publish or Perish, Inc. ISBN091409890X.

External links[edit]

  • How We Got From There to Here: A Story of Real Analysis by Robert Rogers and Eugene Boman
  • A First Course in Analysis by Donald Yau
  • Analysis WebNotes by John Lindsay Orr
  • Interactive Real Analysis by Bert G. Wachsmuth
  • A First Analysis Course by John O'Connor
  • Mathematical Analysis I by Elias Zakon
  • Mathematical Analysis II by Elias Zakon
  • Trench, William F. (2003). Introduction to Real Analysis(PDF). Prentice Hall. ISBN978-0-13-045786-8.
  • Basic Analysis: Introduction to Real Analysis by Jiri Lebl
  • Topics in Real and Functional Analysis by Gerald Teschl, University of Vienna.
Retrieved from 'https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Real_analysis&oldid=916508583'